Analysing the analytic: problems with holistic theories of the evolution of syntax Maggie Tallerman University of Durham maggie.tallerman@durham.ac.uk Until relatively recently, most researchers saw syntax as evolving from an earlier stage with only single words, strung randomly together in a structureless protolanguage. However, other recent work proposes that words are not primary, but emerge from longer, entirely arbitrary strings of sounds, via fractionation (Arbib 2002, 2003). In this analytic approach (Wray 2000, 2002) protolanguage consists of a fixed set of formulaic utterances, used 'for getting things done and for preserving social stability' (Wray 2000). 'Holistic' utterances are unanalysed wholes, with no consistent regularities. For instance, Wray suggests such strings as _tebima_ 'give that to her' and _kumapi_ 'share this with her'. In time, unanalysed material is segmented into meaningful units, when, by chance, phonetically similar substrings occur in several utterances, and can be imbued with a common meaning. In the examples above, _ma_ occurs in both strings, and the meaning 'her' occurs in both formulaic utterances, so _ma_ comes to mean 'her'. In this paper, I dissect the analytic view of early protolanguage, and examine a number of serious flaws in the arguments proposed for it. The main problems are summarized in (1)-(5): 1. Logically, similar substrings must often occur in two (or more) utterances which do NOT share any common elements of meaning at least as many times as they occur in two utterances which DO share semantic elements. For instance, a string _mabali_ also contains the _ma_ sequence, but means 'put that rock down!'. What ensures that _ma_ gets associated with 'her'? Repeated usage alone can't establish all and only the right 'regularities' in the proto-lexicon. 2. Wray suggests that holistic protolanguage is not referential. In fact, it is entirely referential, but all the utterances refer to whole complex events. Whereas vocabulary can be stored by pairing a concept with the arbitrary sound string used to denote it, holistic utterances must be stored by memorizing each complex event and learning which unanalysable string is appropriate at each event. This task is harder, not simpler, than learning words as symbols, and therefore less suitable for an early protolanguage scenario. 3. Although formulaic utterances are common in modern language, and often opaque in their syntax and/or semantics - 'the more, the merrier'; 'he bought a pig in a poke' - they rarely contravene existing syntactic rules. So, an idiom in English could not have OSV word order. This suggests that formulaic utterances are parasitic on existing syntax, emerging from earlier states of syntax via well-known processes (such as grammaticalization). Formulae come from existing grammar, rather than providing tailor-made models for syntax. 4. Wray and Arbib liken formulaic utterances to the 'calls' of primate communication. But primate vocalization is handled by different parts of the brain than human language (Myers 1976, Bradshaw & Rogers 1992), and the homologues of Wernicke's and Broca's areas are not used for vocalization. Thus, the continuity problem persists: holistic calls are not the precursor to language. 5. Words will never appear out of formulae unless the hominids using holistic protolanguage have a) the motor control required to produce recognizable substrings and b) the neural capacity to recognize phonetic strings. But the holistic approach endows these speakers with a greater ability in both areas than would be needed for one-by-one words: the formulae are necessarily longer strings (otherwise they couldn't be broken down) and the speakers need to recognize and utilize subparts of these longer strings. How could this ability exist at the pre-syntactic stage? References Arbib, Michael A., 2002. The Mirror System, imitation, and the evolution of language. In Chrystopher Nehaniv & Kerstin Dautenhahn, (eds.), Imitation in Animals and Artifacts, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Arbib, Michael A., 2003. The evolving Mirror System: a neural basis for language readiness. In Morten H. Christiansen & Simon Kirby, (eds.). Language Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 182-200. Bradshaw, John & Lesley Rogers, 1992. The evolution of lateral asymmetries, language, tool use and intellect. New York: Academic Press. Myers, Ronald E., 1976. Comparative neurology of vocalization and speech: proof of a dichotomy. In Stevan Harnad, Horst D. Steklis, & Jane Lancaster, (eds.). Origins and Evolution of Language and Speech. New York: New York Academy of Sciences. 745-757. Wray, Alison, 2000. Holistic utterances in protolanguage: the link from primates to humans. In Chris Knight, Michael Studdert-Kennedy & James R Hurford, (eds.). The Evolutionary Emergence of Language: Social Function and the Origins of Linguistic Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 285-302. Wray, Alison, 2002. Dual processing in protolanguage: performance without competence. In Alison Wray, (ed.). The Transition to Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 113-137.